Socrates and Theramenes


https://doi.org/10.28995/2686-7249-2024-2-61-76

Full Text:




Abstract

In Diodorus’ work, there is a piece of evidence (dating to 404–403 B.C.), which has no corroborating parallels in other sources and so is often considered not authentic. According to that author, when in Athens during the period of the Thirty regime a conflict occurred between Critias, the leader of extreme oligarchs, and Theramenes, the leader of moderate ones, and the latter was executed as a result of that conflict, Socrates tried (although without success) to come to his aid. There are no other data on friendly relations between the philosopher and the politician in the sources. The article considers the question why in one version of the narrative tradition their names appear to be brought together. Theramenes was conferred extraordinarily contradictory evaluations by ancient authors; he was frequently perceived as an unprincipled person, what is, however, unjustified. The most weighed judgment on him can be found in the Constitution of Athens by Aristotle who emphasizes the main feature in Theramenes’ political position: he was, first of all, a champion of lawfulness, which was constantly violated in late 5th century B.C. by both democrats and oligarchs. But an analogous commitment to rigorous observance of laws was characteristic also of Socrates.


About the Author

I. E. Surikov
Institute of World History, Russian Academy of Sciences; Russian State University for the Humanities
Russian Federation

Igor E. Surikov, Dr. of Sci. (History), professor

32a, Leninsky Av., Moscow, 119334

6, Miusskaya Sq., Moscow, 125047



References

1. Cohen, D. (1995), “The rule of law and democratic ideology in Classical Athens”, in Eder, W., ed., Die athenische Demokratie im 4. Jahrhundert v. Chr.: Vollendung oder Verfall einer Verfassungsform?, Steiner, Stuttgart, Germany, SS. 227–244.

2. Duke, G. (2020), Aristotle and law. The politics of nomos, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.

3. Finley, M.I. (1971), The ancestral constitution, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.

4. Frank, J., Monoson, S.S. (2009), “Why the encomium of Theramenes matters” in Salkever, S., ed., The Cambridge companion to Ancient Greek political thought, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, pp. 243–270.

5. Gagarin, M. (2002), Antiphon the Athenian. Oratory, law, and justice in the age of the Sophists, University of Texas Press, Austin, Texas, USA.

6. Hahm, D.E. (2009), “The mixed constitution in Greek thought”, in Balot, R.K., ed., A companion to Greek and Roman political thought, Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford, UK, pp. 178–198.

7. Hatzfeld, J. (1940), “Socrate au procès des Arginuses”, Revue des études anciennes, vol. 42, pp. 165–171.

8. Joyce, C.J. (2022), Amnesty and reconciliation in late fifth-century Athens. The rule of law under restored democracy, Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh, UK.

9. Krentz, P. (1982), The Thirty at Athens, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, USA.

10. Lintott, A. (2000), “Aristotle and the mixed constitution”, in Brock, R. and Hodkinson, S., eds., Alternatives to Athens. Varieties of political organization and community in Ancient Greece, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, pp. 152–166.

11. Marcaccini, C. (2013), “Rivoluzione oligarchica o restaurazione della democrazia? I Cinquemilia, la πρόκρισις e la patrios politeia”, Klio, Bd. 95, Ht. 2, SS. 405–428.

12. Nails, D. (2002), The people of Plato. A prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics, Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis, USA.

13. Ober, J. (2000), “Living freely as a slave of the law. Notes on why Sokrates lives in Athens”, in Flensted-Jensen, P., Nielsen, T.H. and Rubinstein, L., eds., Polis & Politics. Studies in Ancient Greek history presented to Mogens Herman Hansen on his 60th birthday, August 20, 2000, Museum Tusculanum Press, Copenhagen, Denmark, pp. 541–552.

14. Piérart, M. (1995), “Du règne des philosophes à la souveraineté des lois”, in Eder, W. (ed.), Die athenische Demokratie im 4. Jahrhundert v. Chr.: Vollendung oder Verfall einer Verfassungsform?, Steiner, Stuttgart, Germany, SS. 249–268.

15. Rhodes, P.J. (1985), A Commentary on the Aristotelian “Athenaion Politeia”, Clarendon Press, Oxford, UK.

16. Rhodes, P.J. (2000), “Oligarchs in Athens”, in Brock, R. and Hodkinson, S., eds., Alternatives to Athens. Varieties of political organization and community in Ancient Greece, Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, pp. 119–136.

17. Saldutti, V. (2022), “The mixed constitution of Demetrius Phalereus”, Klio, Bd. 104, Ht. 1, pp. 159–190.

18. Surikov, I.E. (2011a), Anticnaya Gretsiya: politiki v kontexte epokhi. Godina mezhdousobitz [Ancient Greece: Politicians in the context of the epoch. A year of strife], Russkiy fond sodeystviya obrazovaniyu i nauke, Moscow, Russia.

19. Surikov, I.E. (2011b), Sokrat [Socrates], Molodaya gvardiya, Moscow, Russia.

20. Ungern-Sternberg, J., von (2000), “ ‘Die Revolution frißt ihre eignen Kinder’: Kritias vs. Theramenes”, in Burckhardt, L. and Ungern-Sternberg, J., von, eds., Große Prozesse im antiken Athen, Verlag C.H. Beck, München, Germany, SS. 144–156.

21. Vlastos, G. (1991), Socrates, ironist and moral philosopher, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, USA.

22. Whitehead, D. (1993), “1–41, 42–69: A tale of two politeiai”, in Piérart, M., ed., Aristote et Athènes, De Boccard, Paris, France, pp. 25–38.


Supplementary files

For citation: Surikov I.E. Socrates and Theramenes. RSUH/RGGU Bulletin: “Literary Teory. Linguistics. Cultural Studies”, Series. 2024;(2):61-76. https://doi.org/10.28995/2686-7249-2024-2-61-76

Views: 166

Refbacks

  • There are currently no refbacks.


Creative Commons License
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 License.


ISSN 2073-6355 (Print)